What Literature Can Teach Us

Communication and research skills—and how to be a better human being

  • Authors & Texts
  • Top Picks Lists
  • Study Guides
  • Best Sellers
  • Plays & Drama
  • Shakespeare
  • Short Stories
  • Children's Books
  • M.A., English Literature, California State University - Sacramento
  • B.A., English, California State University - Sacramento

Literature is a term used to describe written and sometimes spoken material. Derived from the Latin word  literature  meaning "writing formed with letters," literature most commonly refers to works of the creative imagination, including poetry, drama , fiction , nonfiction , and in some instances, journalism , and song. 

What Is Literature?

Simply put, literature represents the culture and tradition of a language or a people. The concept is difficult to precisely define, though many have tried; it's clear that the accepted definition of literature is constantly changing and evolving.

For many, the word literature suggests a higher art form; merely putting words on a page doesn't necessarily equate to creating literature. A canon is the accepted body of works for a given author. Some works of literature are considered canonical, that is, culturally representative of a particular genre (poetry, prose, or drama).

Literary Fiction vs. Genre Fiction

Some definitions also separate literary fiction from so-called "genre fiction," which includes types such as mystery, science fiction, western, romance, thriller, and horror. Think mass-market paperback.

Genre fiction typically does not have as much character development as literary fiction and is read for entertainment, escapism, and plot, whereas literary fiction explores themes common to the human condition and uses symbolism and other literary devices to convey the author's viewpoint on his or her chosen themes. Literary fiction involves getting into the minds of the characters (or at least the protagonist) and experiencing their relationships with others. The protagonist typically comes to a realization or changes in some way during the course of a literary novel.

(The difference in type does not mean that literary writers are better than genre fiction writers, just that they operate differently.)

Why Is Literature Important?

Works of literature, at their best, provide a kind of blueprint of human society. From the writings of ancient civilizations such as Egypt and China to Greek philosophy and poetry, from the epics of Homer to the plays of William Shakespeare, from Jane Austen and Charlotte Bronte to Maya Angelou , works of literature give insight and context to all the world's societies. In this way, literature is more than just a historical or cultural artifact; it can serve as an introduction to a new world of experience.

But what we consider to be literature can vary from one generation to the next. For instance, Herman Melville's 1851 novel " Moby Dick "   was considered a failure by contemporary reviewers. However, it has since been recognized as a masterpiece and is frequently cited as one of the best works of Western literature for its thematic complexity and use of symbolism. By reading "Moby Dick" in the present day, we can gain a fuller understanding of literary traditions in Melville's time. 

Debating Literature 

Ultimately, we may discover meaning in literature by looking at what the author writes or says and how he or she says it. We may interpret and debate an author's message by examining the words he or she chooses in a given novel or work or observing which character or voice serves as the connection to the reader.

In academia, this decoding of the text is often carried out through the use of  literary theory using a mythological, sociological, psychological, historical, or other approaches to better understand the context and depth of a work.

Whatever critical paradigm we use to discuss and analyze it, literature is important to us because it speaks to us, it is universal, and it affects us on a deeply personal level. 

School Skills

Students who study literature and read for pleasure have a higher vocabulary, better reading comprehension, and better communication skills, such as writing ability. Communication skills affect people in every area of their lives, from navigating interpersonal relationships to participating in meetings in the workplace to drafting intraoffice memos or reports.

When students analyze literature, they learn to identify cause and effect and are applying critical thinking skills. Without realizing it, they examine the characters psychologically or sociologically. They identify the characters' motivations for their actions and see through those actions to any ulterior motives.

When planning an essay on a work of literature, students use problem-solving skills to come up with a thesis and follow through on compiling their paper. It takes research skills to dig up evidence for their thesis from the text and scholarly criticism, and it takes organizational skills to present their argument in a coherent, cohesive manner.

Empathy and Other Emotions

Some studies say that people who read literature have more empathy for others, as literature puts the reader into another person's shoes. Having empathy for others leads people to socialize more effectively, solve conflicts peacefully, collaborate better in the workplace, behave morally, and possibly even become involved in making their community a better place.

Other studies note a correlation between readers and empathy but do not find causation . Either way, studies back the need for strong English programs in schools, especially as people spend more and more time looking at screens rather than books.

Along with empathy for others, readers can feel a greater connection to humanity and less isolated. Students who read literature can find solace as they realize that others have gone through the same things that they are experiencing or have experienced. This can be a catharsis and relief to them if they feel burdened or alone in their troubles.

Quotes About Literature

Here are some quotes about literature from literature giants themselves.

  • Robert Louis Stevenson : "The difficulty of literature is not to write, but to write what you mean; not to affect your reader, but to affect him precisely as you wish."
  • Jane Austen, "Northanger Abbey" : "The person, be it gentleman or lady, who has not pleasure in a good novel, must be intolerably stupid."
  • William Shakespeare, "Henry VI" : “I’ll call for pen and ink and write my mind.”
  • What Is the Canon in Literature?
  • 5 Novel Setting Maps for Classic American Literature
  • What's the Difference Between Classical and Classic Literature?
  • Why We Don't Read
  • What Is a Modern Classic in Literature?
  • Notable Authors of the 19th Century
  • The Basic Characteristics of Effective Writing
  • American Author Maps: Informational Texts in the English Classroom
  • Genres in Literature
  • AP English Literature and Composition Course and Exam Information
  • An Introduction to Metafiction
  • High Interest-Low Reading Level Books for Reluctant Readers
  • SAT Literature Subject Test Information
  • Feminist Literary Criticism
  • Interior Monologues
  • 10 Strategies to Increase Student Reading Comprehension

By clicking “Accept All Cookies”, you agree to the storing of cookies on your device to enhance site navigation, analyze site usage, and assist in our marketing efforts.

  • Search Menu
  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Landscape Art and Architecture
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • Gender and Sexuality in Art
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Social History
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Culture
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Lifestyle, Home, and Garden
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Politics
  • Law and Society
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Medical Oncology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Ethics
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Critical Care Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Study and Communication Skills in Life Sciences
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Audio Processing
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist and Conservationist Organizations (Environmental Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Network Science
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Political and Economic Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Ethics
  • Business Strategy
  • Business History
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and Government
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Social Issues in Business and Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic History
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Philosophy of Economics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Social Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Theory
  • Politics and Law
  • Public Policy
  • Public Administration
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Developmental and Physical Disabilities Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution

The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Literature

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

20 Literature and Knowledge

John Gibson is associate professor of philosophy at the University of Louisville. He is the author of Fiction and the Weave of Life (Oxford UP, 2007) and coeditor of A Sense of the World: Essays on Fiction, Narrative and Knowledge and The Literary Wittgenstein. He is currently working on a new book titled Poetry, Metaphor, and Nonsense: An Essay on Meaning.

  • Published: 02 September 2009
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This article presents thoughts about the role of literature as a source of knowledge. It is common to claim that in works of literature we find some of the most powerful representations of reality our culture has to offer. According to this view, the literary perspective is the definitive human perspective and works of literature represent cognitive achievements and embody ways of knowing the world. This article attempts to give a sense of how powerful the arguments against the cognitivist view of literature are and to bring to light how the philosopher beholden to it might respond to them. It argues that we must accept that literature's particular manner of engaging with reality is sui generis because it constitutes its own form of cognitive insight and shows that literature's cognitive achievements are intimately bound up with its aesthetic achievements.

It is common to claim that in works of literature we find some of the most powerful representations of reality our culture has to offer. This claim is central to the general humanistic conception of the value of the literary work of art: it is at least partly in the business of revealing to readers something of consequence about the nature of their shared world. According to this view, the literary perspective (and the artistic perspective more generally) is the definitive human perspective: the standpoint from which we are best able to bring to light the range of values, desires, frustrations, experiences, and practices that define the human situation. On this view, works of literature, at least when they live up to their promise, represent cognitive achievements: they embody ways of knowing the world.

But in developing a literary tradition, we have come to devise a rather curious way of going about revealing our world. As the saying goes, literature is “the book of life.” And what is curious, simply put, is that when we open this book we find it to be filled with fictions . That works of imaginative literature—the sort of literature I discuss here—speak about the fictional rather than the real is hardly news. To be sure, one would think that literature's use of the creative imagination constitutes rather than refutes its claim to cognitive value: it is the tool with which literature builds its vision of our world. But the challenge the philosopher of literature faces is one of explaining just how this may be. How is it, exactly, that a textual form that speaks of fictions can tell us something of consequence about reality? Why is it that we have come to find that writing about fictions can be a powerful way of opening up a window on our world? We tend to think that it can be, of course. But as with all philosophical challenges, explaining this with a respectable degree of sophistication turns out to be a difficult affair.

The problem runs deeper than literature's interest in the imaginary and the unreal. It is not only that when we look between the covers of a novel we find descriptions of fictions. We also notice a conspicuous absence of all those tools, devices, and techniques we commonly take to be essential to the search for truth and knowledge: argumentation, the offering of evidence, the setting forth of “the facts,” the proffering of premises, the derivation of conclusions, and so on (see Stolnitz 1992 ; John 1998 ; Lamarque and Olsen 1994 ; Diffey 1988 ). Needless to say, the ways in which works of history, philosophy, and science—paradigm cases of works of inquiry —make use of these devices and techniques vary considerably. It may even be the case that they are all, like literature, irreducibly narratological in form—this is a fairly popular claim in contemporary postmodern culture (see White 1978 ; Fish 1980 ). But works of inquiry weave their narratives in ways very unlike literature, and it is the particular way a narrative is woven that makes the difference here. Literature standardly constructs fictional narratives that have dramatic structures; works of inquiry standardly attempt to construct factual narratives that have argumentative (or evidentiary) structures. This would seem an important difference. And the challenge is to show that literary works can have a claim to cognitive value in the absence of those features of writing commonly taken to be the stuff of the pursuit of knowledge. For in their absence, precisely what aspect of literary works do we point toward that justifies treating them as players in the pursuit of knowledge? What do we find in works of literature that even entitles us to think that they wish to be read for knowledge? Again, we tend to think that there is something, but identifying precisely what is the challenge.

It is also now generally understood that to call into question the view of literary works as vehicles of knowledge is not thereby to embrace a form of literary philistinism, namely, the picture of literary works as entertaining but ultimately trivial playthings. Since the rise of various brands of literary formalism and aestheticism in the past century, philosophers and literary theorists have done much to show that there is a powerful alternative to this socalled “cognitivist” tradition of speaking about literature, one that has an equal claim to being a defense of the value of literature, of why we take literature so seriously . Philosophers and literary theorists of an anticognitivist bent do not deny that literary representations are very often profound, perceptive, aweinspiring, and so forth. The thought is rather that while we will have a very hard time accounting for this profundity (etc.) in cognitive terms—say, a profundity of insight—it is altogether easy to do so in aesthetic terms. It is also likely more natural, for literary works are, after all, works of art. Indeed, an aesthetic view of literature can even urge that it is to commit what Gilbert Ryle would call a category error to try to account for the value of literary representations in cognitive terms: it amounts to a silly desire to carry over to aesthetic domains terms meant to account for the value of representations in philosophical and scientific domains.

Whether or not one quite agrees with this, it does have a certain intuitive appeal, for we have a vocabulary that works perfectly well for talking about works of art—an aesthetic vocabulary—and it is not altogether ridiculous to think that to apply the vocabulary we use to account for the value of works of inquiry also to literature is simply to misunderstand the nature of what we are talking about. At any rate, the possibility of offering a fully aesthetic theory of literature marks the presence of a more direct, and certainly less challenging, way to account for the value of literature. It is hard to imagine a literary cognitivist who has not at one time felt its appeal, who has not at least for a moment thought that she may have taken the wrong route to arrive at her defense of the value of literature.

This is the challenge I address in this chapter. I hope to give a sense of how powerful the arguments against the cognitivist view of literature are, but also to bring to light how the philosopher beholden to it might respond to them. More precisely, I argue that we must accept that literature's particular manner of engaging with reality is sui generis , so much so, in fact, that it constitutes its own form of cognitive insight. This implies, among others things, that we abandon what we might call the philosophy-by-other-means view of literature, and in general any defense of literary cognitivism that attempts to model literature on a theory of how other sorts of texts can have cognitive value (e.g., by showing them to mimic philosophical works, perhaps by being a thought experiment in literary guise, a sort of dramatic “proof,” an exercise in moral reasoning by example, and other like things we in no obvious sense find when we look inside the majority of literary works). I also hope to show that literature's cognitive achievements are intimately bound up with its aesthetic achievements. The humanist need not turn her back to the aesthetic dimension of literary works when defending the cognitive value she believes many of them store. Rather, the humanist must embrace it, for it is here that literary works effect their particular enlightenment.

Before beginning, note that the debate on the cognitive value of literature does not concern a mere epistemological puzzle. It begins with this, but it brings something much more important to the attention of the philosopher of literature. It opens up a discussion of the general cultural significance of the literary work of art. Perhaps the issue of whether literary works can offer a precise sort of knowledge is not even what is really at stake in this debate. In asking whether works of literature can offer knowledge, we are asking to have the worldly interest we take in art vindicated. What is at stake here is our ability to articulate what amounts to a satisfactory account of the interplay of art and life itself. I do not attempt anything as grand as this here. But I do hope that what I say about the epistemological issue will give a sense of how one can use it as a tool for exploring the variety of ways in which literature and life take an interest in one another.

The Textual Constraint

We can learn any number of things from works of imaginative literature, though many are trivial and of little literary relevance. From a master stylist, I might learn how to write with wit and grace; from an Elizabethan drama, I can gain insight into the English of an older age; from a novel of dazzling inventiveness, I can acquire knowledge of possibilities of description and conceptualization. The list is nearly endless. If the problem of literary cognitivism were simply one of identifying something— anything —we can learn from literature, it would be a very dull debate, for it is impossible to imagine how one could fail to arrive at a positive response to the question. But the challenge is not merely to find a way of showing that we can leave our literary encounters with “more information,” so baldly put. We do, in countless ways. Rather, the challenge is to reveal literary works themselves to have as one of their goals the offering of a form of understanding, and this is a quite different and much more difficult matter. The claim to cognitive acquisition on the part of a reader is of little literary relevance if not tethered to a complementary claim to the effect that what the reader has learned is a lesson the literary work actually puts on offer. It is only in this sense that the question is a proper literary one, that is, a question that stands to reveal something about the nature of the literary work of art.

This is not always as appreciated as it should be. One finds much ink spilt on how works of literature might help improve our faculty of imagination (Currie 1998 ; Harold 2003 ), develop our cognitive skills (Novitz 1987 ), discover what we would think, feel, or value if in another's shoes (Walton 1997 ; Currie 1998 ), become more sympathetic and adept moral reasoners (Nussbaum 1990 ), and so on. These are genuine cognitive achievements, and literature can certainly help us in our pursuit of them. But, like the above examples, they tend to say too much about readers and too little about literary works. Since literary works are for obvious reasons rarely about the imagination, cognitive skills, or emotions of their readers, to gesture toward these things in an attempt to defend the thesis of literary cognitivism is to gesture toward the wrong thing. The question is primarily textual: it concerns the nature of the literary, of what we find of cognitive significance when we look inside a literary work. It is only about readers—about the ways in which their minds and morals can be improved through their encounters with literature—in a secondary, derivative sense.

Consider a classics student who, having been asked to read Plato's Symposium , returns to his teacher and claims to have learned much from it. The teacher asks the student to explain exactly what he has learned, to which he replies, “a considerable amount of Attic Greek and some fine metaphors for drunkenness.” He very well may have learned this—one can find all of this in Plato's dialogue—and he might be all the better for it. But naturally the teacher will think that the student has missed the point of the assignment. The student has learned something, but he has not learned it from Plato . This is because what he claims to have learned makes no reference at all to what we might describe as the cognitive labor of Plato's dialogue, to the lesson it wishes to impart, to the insight it struggles to articulate—assuming, as I am, that Plato intends in that dialogue to illuminate the nature of love and not the grammar of Attic Greek or our capacity to speak in metaphors. Indeed, the student's response fails to show an understanding of the text, which is what we expect a claim of cognitive acquisition to reveal.

Likewise, responses to the problem of literary cognitivism that put all of the emphasis on how readers might become more successful imaginers, emoters, and reasoners are, in the end, much more sophisticated versions of the mistake of the classics student. It is valuable to have accounts of how engagements with the literary affect readers in morally and intellectually positive ways. We do live in a culture in which art is at times thought to be of no more significance than its ability to amuse, and these accounts do much to counter literary philistinism of this brand. But as a response to the question of whether literary works themselves have cognitive aspirations, they are not very satisfying. In fact, they are largely silent on this matter.

It is true, as Berys Gaut argues, that we are able “to apply the imaginative world of the fiction to the real world, and thereby to discover truths about the world” (2006: 123). We do this often when moved by a work. We turn from it and find ourselves now capable of seeing the world in its light, and this can be an important source of cognitive insight. After we read George Eliot's Middlemarch or Shakespeare's Henry IV , for example, we find ourselves able to identify all the Casaubons and Falstaffs who inhabit our world. These characters are, in their proper literary mode of presentation, creatures of pure fiction and so without any intrinsic cognitive value. But we can use these characters as tools for approaching reality, treating them as lenses through which we can attempt to perceive human character more clearly. This, in turn, can open up a way of acquiring truths about human nature, of coming to discover something about it. But while this may be a significant feature of what we do with literary works, it is not a particularly good strategy for a defense of literary cognitivism. If the acquisition of truth depends on the reader applying aspects of a fictional world to the real one, then presumably that truth is not given expression in the work itself, and so the work cannot quite put it on offer. We may come to learn about the world when we do what Gaut claims we do. But we haven't quite come to learn about the world from literature . And this is what we want answered: Can literature itself record, document, or bear witness to something about our cognitive relation to reality? We miss the point if we try to explain this by describing ways in which readers rather than literary works perform the cognitive labor here.

This is a problem with many popular versions of the socalled propositional theory of literary cognitivism (for a discussion of its history, see Lamarque and Olsen 1994 ). In an influential and clever defense of this, Peter Kivy writes:

Now if one thinks, as I do, that part of the reader's literary appreciation consists in confirming and disconfirming for himself the general thematic statements he perceives in fictional works he reads, sometimes unaided, sometimes through the help of literary critics, one will see why it is quite compatible with the Propositional Theory that such confirmation and disconfirmation are part of appreciation, and that appreciation is the job, if I may so put it, of the reader, not the critic qua critic. The critic's job, qua critic, is, among other things, to make available to the reader whatever hypothesis the fictional work may, directly or indirectly, propose. It is the reader's job to appreciate them, in part by confirming or disconfirming them for himself. (1997: 125, emphasis original; see also New 1999 : 116–20)

When we find ourselves struck by a literary representation, we tend to find a suggestion in it, a clue as to how we may view the real world. Though the characters we find in a literary work are fictional, the particular ways in which an author invests their lives with meaning, their actions with urgency, their relationships with consequence, always suggest to the reader a way of regarding actual human affairs. The production of these visions and suggestions is typically a matter of literature's thematic rendering of its subject, say, the way in which a certain work configures “suffering,” “jealousy,” or “joy” as this sort of experience. Through the force of its thematic representation of a region of human concern, literature is able to hold up for appreciation a finely wrought vision of human experience and circumstance. And we tend to have an interest in subjecting these visions to cognitive scrutiny, in asking whether our world is really like that, or whether it would be better if it were. Much of this is surely right, and to this extent positions such as Kivy's capture an important dimension of our appreciation of literary works.

Note, however, that Kivy (and this line of thought more generally) accepts that literary themes are of no intrinsic cognitive significance. To build the bridge to truth, we have to engage in an activity that is rather suspicious from the literary point of view. We (or the critic) must convert a literary theme into a philosophical claim, a “hypothesis”—this is the act of rendering a theme in propositional form—which we can then go on to scrutinize for truth (e.g., by casting the representation of jealousy in Othello in terms of a claim to the effect that “jealousy can destroy what we hold most dear”). If this is so, it is hard not to be left with the feeling that the process of conversion that is the mechanism of cognitive acquisition here illicitly replaces literary content with philosophical content, and that in so doing, it moves the object of appreciation from the text to what is ultimately outside it. We do not in any literal sense find these “hypotheses” in literary works, and thus our appreciation of these hypotheses, though occasioned by our encounters with the literary, cannot itself be properly literary. When we convert a theme into the form of a hypothesis (or proposition), we are already once removed from the work, and when we begin scrutinizing this hypothesis for truth, we soon find ourselves twice removed. It seems clear that the labor put into forging the connection to truth is, again, performed almost entirely by the reader rather than by the work, and thus we face the old problem.

What these reflections bring to view is a basic constraint on what can count as a response to the problem of literary cognitivism. We might call it the “textual constraint” and treat it as telling us that a satisfactory account of a proper feature of a literary work requires that whatever property we attribute to a text—say, the property of being cognitively valuable—be an actual property of the text: something we come into contact with when we explore the interior of the work. It must be a part of its content , broadly construed. So if a certain point or insight is not in the work, then, according to this textual constraint, we cannot claim to have learned that point from the work. Of course, novels, at least good ones, make us think. But the important question from the literary standpoint is what we think about when we think about a work. And if it is something not quite in the work, then that something cannot be invoked to explain a value of that work. If we fail to respect this, we are ignoring the text, much as the classics student ignored Plato. We are merely commenting on how we can enlist the text in our personal intellectual pursuits and ultimately saying nothing about how the literary work of art itself might embody knowledge of the world.

The Loss of the World

It is here that the problem begins to take the form of a proper philosophical challenge. According to the textual constraint, we must limit our search for cognitive value to the work itself, looking inside rather than away from it. And what we find is that virtually all the resources contemporary philosophy has given us for describing the “inside” of literary works appear to make impossible the claim that we can find in them something sufficiently real to give support to the thesis of literary cognitivism.

Prior to the twentieth century, the tradition of broadly humanistic philosophizing about art—beginning with Aristotle and extending through the German and English romantic traditions—was canonical, though always with the occasional detractor. When philosophers spoke of art, there was, in addition to compulsory observations on the nature of beauty and other aesthetic features of art, almost always an important word offered on art's general cultural significance, on the ways in which works of art articulate an insight into our capacity to achieve freedom, attain moral selfhood, reveal the universal implicit in the particular, find meaning in a world without much of a point, and so forth (see Davis 1996 ; Weston 2001 ).

But when philosophy took its initial steps toward the socalled “linguistic turn” of the twentieth century, discussions of the nature of literature began to focus on the semantic and referential features of literary language rather than on its power of cultural articulation, and a very different habit of speaking about literature began to emerge in philosophical circles. Perhaps the decisive first step in this shift was Gottlob Frege's 1892 publication of “Über Sinn und Bedeutung” [On Sense and Reference], in which we find the following claim:

In hearing an epic poem we are … interested only in the sense of the sentences and the images and feelings thereby aroused. The question of truth would cause us to abandon aesthetic delight for the attitude of scientific investigation. Hence it is a matter of no concern for us whether the name “Odysseus” has reference, so long as we accept the poem as a work of art. (1970: 63)

What we find announced here is a view of the language of literary works that has the consequence of severing whatever internal connection we once thought might exist between literary works and extraliterary reality. Works of imaginative literature retain the “sense” of our terms, and thus the words we find in them preserve their standard meanings. Literature and what we might call “worlddirected” texts (e.g., historical works, which attempt to refer to or otherwise represent reality) share the same language, generally put; they both participate in the same Sinn . But literary language stays on the level of Sinn , whereas in its standard (empirical) uses, language takes the extra step of applying these words to the actual world. Thus, literature is, if not quite self-referential, at least not interested in referring to anything real, to anything beyond itself. And if this is so, then, as Frege puts it, the “question of truth,” central to so much of the humanist tradition, is barred from our appreciation of literature.

There are few Fregeans around today, but the very general orientation toward literature we find in “Über Sinn und Bedeutung” is still with us. Frege's view of literature as a sort of pure “sense” language has not aged well. (In fact, it may not even be Frege's view, since it is often argued that there can be no genuine sense without reference on Frege's model, but this is how contemporary literary aesthetics has received him.) Literature does, on many views, have truth and reference, just of a rather deviant sort. What we find in the tradition that arose after Frege is that the notions of truth and reference have been relocated to the fictional dimension of literature, in order to explain the ways in which works of literature function to generate and state “truths” about fictional worlds. Thus, these notions no longer serve the traditional humanistic purpose of marking the means by which literary works speak about reality. In this respect, while philosophers have recovered from Frege a notion of “literary reference,” the wedge Frege drove between literature and truth is very much still in place. The consequence of this, of course, is that literature is made mute about the stirrings of extraliterary reality.

To give a sampling of prominent recent theories of fiction, in socalled speech-act approaches it is argued that writing a work of fiction is a form of nondeceptive pretense in which authors pretend to state as fact what is known to be untrue (Searle 1974 –75; Beardsley 1981 ). In this sense, literature speaks, simply with a wink, about what is not, and so, while not in the business of telling lies, does not go about stating worldly truths. Or we find accounts that claim that literary works project a special class of possible worlds, namely, fictional worlds (Lewis 1978 ; Pavel 1986 ; Doležal 1998 ). The problem of fiction in literature here becomes somewhat like the problem of counterfactuals in the philosophy of language, a matter of describing the mechanism that allows a writer to describe actions and events that never actually occurred (or allows a reader to understand statements made about them, e.g., how we are able to make truthvalued and referential statements about nonactual states of affairs). And we have the extraordinarily influential “make-believe” account of fiction (Walton 1990 ). Here it is argued that just as children use sticks and stones as swords and bombs in a game of make-believe, when adults read literature they use words in much the same way. We do not believe what we read in a work of imaginative fiction, since we cannot believe a sentence (or a text largely composed of sentences) we know is not true. But we can make-believe them, and so we treat the descriptions in a literary work as props for our imaginative involvement in the story line, using nonepistemic attitudes (e.g., “imagining that”) to ground the possibility of appreciating a fiction as a something though we know all the while that it is really nothing at all. (For a survey of contemporary theories of fiction, see Davies 2000 .)

One should notice that none of these theories proposes the patently absurd idea that works of imaginative literature speak exclusively about the imaginary and the unreal, a claim that would imply that when William Faulkner wrote As I Lay Dying he invented not only Addie Bundren but also Mississippi, wagons, and death. The picture we get from these theories is that the bits and pieces of reality we find woven into works of fiction play a nonepistemic role in these works. They are used to give texture to the fictional world of the work rather than to represent or state truths about actual states of affairs. We do criticize a novel that uses, for instance, New York as its setting yet fails to get straight the difference between Downtown and Uptown. But this is a critique of the setting's accuracy, and it is done along the lines in which we criticize a set in a play rather than an argument to the effect that the literary work attempts to make truthclaims about the world and fails in so doing. Saying so much—claiming that accuracy of worldly background and setting in works of imaginative fiction is straightforwardly truthfunctional or referential—would be akin to saying that the set in a production of A Street Car Named Desire functioned to make truthclaims about New Orleans, which is plain silly.

What we find in this shift in twentieth-century literary aesthetics from traditional humanistic concerns to an overriding interest in the logic and semantics of fictional discourse is that philosophy has developed a vocabulary for speaking about literature that has made it even more difficult to give sense to the thesis of literary cognitivism. There are other theories of fiction around than those just surveyed. But in virtually all of them we see a commitment to the old Fregean move of denying that literature has realworldly truth and reference. The consequence is that it gives an air of nonsense to the idea that literary language might actually be able to tell us something of cognitive significance about the world. For if it does not speak about reality—if it sends its words and description to fictional rather than real addresses—how could it possibly be revelatory of reality? In this respect, the problem for the literary cognitivist is not merely that literary works refuse to use the tools of inquiry to build support for their claims, as discussed above. Literature does not even make claims , so there is really nothing for it to support.

This is likely one of the reasons that attempts to defend literary cognitivism such as Gaut's and Kivy's are so prominent. At first glance, the sort of insight they argue works of literature can offer may seem odd from the literary point of view, arguing as they do that readers rather than literary works perform the lion's share of cognitive labor. But given the notion of fiction with which so much contemporary philosophy operates, we can also see why moves such as theirs are so alluring. If what we have to say about literary fiction is that it concerns possible worlds, or that it casts the content of a literary work as an object of make-believe, then the idea of finding reality disclosed through a literary work is made utterly mysterious. If this is so, then it appears obligatory to look outside the text to establish a connection with truth and knowledge.

And so we arrive at the heart of the problem: according to the textual constraint, we must look within the work to ground literary cognitivism, and this seems to be precisely what we cannot do. Literary language has no declarative power, and thus it is not in the business of telling us about the nature of our world. It is true that works of fiction can embody a vision of aspects of human experience and circumstance: Bartleby the Scrivener is among the most potent representations we have of alienation; Othello , of jealousy. But visions are, from the epistemic point of view, just that: mere pictures, representations of life that are often powerful, moving, even beautiful, but for all that, cognitively neutral. Thus, something outside the work must be invoked to build the bridge between these visions and worldly truth. But the moment we look outside the work to build this bridge, we have implicitly conceded the defeat of literary cognitivism. We might console ourselves by remarking on the ways in which we can enlist literary works in our extraliterary cognitive pursuits—as we saw above, this is rather easy to do—and so we needn't fear that literary philistinism is a consequence of this. But given what philosophy tells us it means for a text to be fictional, for a use of language to be literary, it is hard indeed to see how we might give life to the thesis of literary cognitivism.

Moving the Debate Ahead

Those of us who still feel drawn to the idea that literary works are sources of worldly illumination will likely think that in all of this something crucial has been left unmentioned, and that this something is essential to the thesis of literary cognitivism. I think that this is right, and for the remainder of this chapter I try to identify just what this something is.

What should strike one as initially suspicious in the way the problem is set up in the debate is that it seems to make the case for literary cognitivism hang on whether we can apply to literature the vocabulary we have for explaining how works of inquiry illuminate reality. Though this is rarely made explicit by the major players in the debate, one does have a sense that the discussion gets afoot by looking at standard sorts of text with cognitive value—scientific, philosophical, and so on—and then wondering whether works of art can do what they do, at least at some level and to some extent. This is a questionable way of approaching the matter. I assume that painting is a paradigm case of art. But I also assume that no sensible person would try to account for the artistic value of music by asking whether what we find in paintings can also be found in symphonies. We are likely guilty of a similar sin if we hear the question of whether literary works have cognitive value as asking us solely whether they can offer truth and knowledge. What I think we see in the above arguments for anticognitivism is the poverty of the vocabulary of truth and knowledge when applied to literature (for similar critiques see Lamarque and Olsen 1994 ; Lamarque 1996 , 2006). But perhaps the literary cognitivist does not need this vocabulary.

Yet what is meant by “truth” and “knowledge” here? What these anticognitivist arguments deny that the literary work possesses is a standard (and significant) sort of knowledge. This standard sort is often called “propositional” or “conceptual” knowledge, depending on the particular spin one gives it. If literature were able to offer us this sort of knowledge, then the story we should be able to tell about it would be something like the following. If we were to acquire what appears to be a potential candidate for knowledge from Fyodor Dostoyevsky's presentation of, say, suffering in Notes from Underground , then this work would in one way or another have to assert something about what suffering is . This would be done by offering a proposition—implicitly, in the case of works of art—to the effect that suffering, or a species thereof, is “thus and such a thing,” say, a condition of mind in which one's world and one's self appear at once alien and revolting. If this happened, we would then be given epistemic access to a new concept of suffering or, at any rate, a refinement of the one we already possess. Literary works, however, lacking declarative power, and much else in addition, are not in the business of articulating truths of this variety, and thus they cannot be (or do not wish to be) vehicles of the sort of propositional-conceptual knowledge tied to it.

In recent years there has been a steady proliferation of philosophers who have noticed that art has an important power to offer forms of insight that in no obvious way rest upon the proffering of knowledge of this standard sort—in fact, that do not consist at all in the stating of truths about the way our world is. And this, I think, offers the literary cognitivist an important clue. Metaphors, as Ted Cohen has argued, can give expression to a new way of feeling and thinking about a familiar subject of human concern. When I offer you a successful metaphor, the metaphor holds in place a certain cognitive and emotional orientation toward the world (rather than states a truth about it), and it thus functions to “invite you to join a community with me, an intimate community whose bond is our common feeling about something” (Cohen 2004 : 236). Noël Carroll has argued that the ethical value of art is a matter not of its offering a body of moral knowledge but of its capacity to enrich the knowledge we already possess: “[I]n mobilizing what we already know and what we already feel, the narrative artwork can become an occasion for us to deepen our understanding of what we already know and feel” (1998: 142). And Richard Eldridge has argued at length for art's capacity to present to us “materials about which we do not know exactly how to feel and judge” (2003: 226). Works of art do not resolve this material—say, a striking representation of a morally ambiguous practice—into a proposition that tells us what to feel and think about it. The force of their presentation of this material resides in the very act of working through it, for in so doing works of art bring to light the “complex texture of our human lives” (230). (For a similarly spirited accounts, see Graham 1995 ; John 2003 ; Harrison 1991 ; see also chapter 10 this volume.)

There is much to admire in these positions. In each of them the insight is tied to an artwork's aesthetic handling of its content. Works of art, thus conceived, illuminate the world not by pausing from their artistic pursuits and mimicking a work of inquiry (e.g., by arguing, acting as a thought experiment, or dealing out claims about the nature of this or that). Rather, this illumination is inseparable from the metaphoric and narratological dimensions of works of art. These philosophers urge that if we look deep enough, we can discover a certain cognitive force in these features of art, which has the attractive consequence of showing us how to allow art to be just that yet find ground upon which to build an account of its cognitive value. Like Carroll, I want to argue that literature's cognitive value resides in its ability not to offer knowledge but rather to act upon the knowledge we already possess. And like Eldridge and Cohen, I want to claim that the form of insight we get from this concerns not truth, properly socalled, but a certain cognitive orientation toward the “texture” of human experience and circumstance. Like all three, I hope to show that literature's ability to do this resides in the work itself, in the power of the visions of life it holds in place.

Before I can explain how this is so or precisely what this means, I need to introduce the sort of understanding I shall argue that literature is especially able to offer. The intuition I want to exploit is that there is much more to “understanding” than the possession of knowledge of the propositional or conceptual variety. This is perhaps obvious: there is a great variety of ways of understanding and knowing the world that cannot be captured exclusively in terms of conceptual knowledge (knowing-how is one example). But I have a specific sort of understanding in mind. It is not an alternative to conceptual knowledge. It is rather a sort of understanding that must be added to it if we are to understand certain aspects of our world fully . The aspects I have in mind are of a broadly moral import. They are those that designate sorts of human practice and experience in which questions of value, of response, of feeling, come into play: joy, jealousy, suffering, love, as well as racism, exploitation, self-fulfillment, trust, and the like—many of the things that are given expression in literary works of art. Let me explain.

Understanding and Merely Knowing

To hurry my discussion along, I offer a few examples, all rather farfetched, but I will bring them down to earth in a moment. Each of the examples concerns a certain failure of response. These failures in turn raise a question about the conditions under which we are willing to attribute genuine understanding to an agent.

Imagine that you are crossing a busy midday intersection when a large bus speeds past the red light and into the crowd of people directly in front of you. Bodies are thrown and lives are lost; quite a few people are clearly in a bad way. Next to you is a man who quickly produces a cell phone. He begins to dial. A sense of relief, if that is the right word, begins to wash over you: help will soon be on its way. But when the person the man has called answers, you hear the man say, “Hey Pete, I just saw the damndest thing … ” Now imagine the same scene, but after the accident the man turns to you and says, in absolute sincerity, “someone really should call for help.” But he starts walking off, intently navigating his way round the wounded, his cell phone tucked securely in his pocket. Last, imagine not the accident but the moment before it. You and this odd man see the bus approaching. There is just enough time. You rush to push the people ahead of you out of harm's way. The man, however, pulls you back to safety and says, with a hint of tough knowingness, “it ain't worth it.” You reply, “Of course it is!” But it is too late. In all three cases, assume, the man does not strike you as fully aware of what is wrong with his responses. When he notices the look of disgust on your face, he appears not embarrassed (or defiant or amused) but genuinely nonplussed. His expression is one of, “What?”

There are many things wrong with this man. Most are of the standard moral variety: he is likely in possession of a rather vicious character; he seems not to care much for what one should care for greatly; he turns a tragedy into an anecdote—and much else besides. But while these examples raise moral issues, my interest here is not quite in their moral dimension, narrowly conceived. Rather, I am especially interested in how the moral failure here suggests a certain cognitive failure. It is a failure of moral understanding, to be sure. But it is the issue of understanding itself that I wish to explore.

The first, perhaps obvious, point is that in each of these cases the failure we find in the man is not a failure of knowledge , at least in the minimal sense in which we ascribe knowledge to someone. He, like you, knows what has happened. If he did not know this, his responses would have been of an altogether different nature. He would have done nothing instead of an odd thing. He knows that there has been an accident, that there is a question as to whether one should risk one's safety to help others, that those suffering are not actors or automatons but people made of flesh and blood, and so on. If these are among the “truths” of the matter, then the man is in possession of these truths. If you were to put them to him in the form of propositions (“Do you see that there are people who are hurt, that they require help …?”), then he would assent to them. He knows, in this basic epistemic sense, what you know.

The question we naturally want to ask is this: Given that the man knows all this, how could he respond as he did? The strangeness of his response, of his particular way of acknowledging the knowledge he shares with us, gives us a reason to think that the difference between you and this man is not only moral but also intellectual: there is something he just does not get (or that the two of you get very differently), for if he understood the event as you did, he would have responded to your look of disapprobation not with confusion but a snarl, a mischievous grin— something that would have revealed that he is aware of how one should act in such a moment and that he just did not care to act thus. But this is precisely what you do not find in him. In a crucial respect, he seems oblivious , over and above the respects in which he appears simply callous. His failure to lead his knowledge though the appropriate channels of response suggests that at some level there is a significant divergence in cognitive orientation toward the same event. He either does not understand something you do, or he understands it in a way that is fundamentally different than you do. Either way, there is something in your mind that cannot be found in his. What might it be, exactly?

There are many ways one could explain this, and I do not want to wander off into arcane corners of epistemology and cognitive philosophy in search of them. For the sake of simplicity, I distinguish two basic sorts of understanding this example suggests, with the hope that they will suffice in a general way to bring to view an interesting point about cognition. Each form of understanding concerns a grasp of what, one might say, “counts” (in this and the following, I draw from Mulhall 1994 and especially Cavell 1969 ).

In the first sense, call it the criterial , to know is to know what counts as an instance of something: one thing a stone, another a table, that an expression of suffering, this of joy. Understanding in this sense is made evident by our success in extending our concepts out into the world and correctly placing particulars under their scope. This sort of understanding records a facility with dividing the world up accurately and correctly describing its particulars, a grasp of “what something is” as a success of identifying this as that sort of thing. It is a matter, simply put, of the individuation and identity of the bits of the world before us. The man's behavior meets this condition for ascribing understanding to him. He shows by his elementary success of identification—that what you and he witnessed is of the kind that it is, that the wounded are in the state that they are, and so forth—that he is in possession of this sort of awareness.

But the example also gives us reason to think that, without supplementation, this form of understanding is decidedly incomplete. Indeed, there is something rather “mere” about it. It is necessary, of course, for without the capacity to represent the world aright, we have no chance of responding to the world as we should. As a designation of a form of cognitive awareness, this criterial understanding marks one of the most basic orientations we can have toward our world, that of simply being able to identify its furniture correctly. To meet this condition for counting as a knower, all one must do is reveal that one is in possession of the relevant concepts and that one can relate them to the world in a certain way. We expect much more from a knower than this. To count as genuinely understanding what one knows in this “mere” sense, one must grasp something else.

To borrow an ugly term from ethics, for a moment at least, we might call the second sense in which understanding is linked to a notion of what counts axiological . It is in this respect that the odd man does not quite understand what you do. Here “counting” is, broadly put, a matter of value—of how something counts as an object of concern, as a site of significance, of how and why it matters . If the criterial sense emphasizes our ability to represent the world correctly, the axiological sense highlights the capacity to see the consequence of those aspects of the human world so represented. This sort of understanding designates an awareness of what is at stake when we represent the world in certain ways; it reveals a grasp of how an object or event should function to engage us with the world when we describe it as thus and such. To this extent, it is a distinctly cultural form of understanding, for it has as its target not merely “objects” and their identity conditions but also the values, cares, and concerns that define the character of our particularly human practices and experiences.

Understanding is never valueneutral, is never merely conceptual, at least not when it concerns human reality. To count as possessing full understanding of something, we must reveal not only that we have the relevant concepts and representational capacities. We must also show that we are alive to those patterns of value, significance, and meaning that are woven into the aspects of the world we otherwise “merely” know. We do this not by revealing that we are in possession of the right propositions or descriptions, say, by asserting, correctly, “an ambulance is needed” or “these people are in pain.” In fact, when we attempt to elaborate this sort of understanding, to bring into full view just what it is, we tend to do so by depicting not what one says but what one does when one knows something. We offer examples of how one invests oneself in the particular scene one knows (or refuses to, e.g., in characters such as Bartleby). That is, we describe a type of response, a kind of gesture, that embodies this understanding. We give an account of how one acknowledges what one knows, of how a piece of knowledge should function to configure the knower as certain sort of agent . And for this, a picture, a vision, of human activity is necessary, not the elaboration of a concept or principle.

Note that a moral response, an act of acknowledgment, is a kind of dramatic gesture and that the understanding it embodies itself has a certain dramatic structure. An act of acknowledgment is a way of giving life to what it is that we know, of bringing it into the public world, not unlike the way in which an actor gives life to a character, or an artist manifests an inner emotion through a perfectly rendered expression. Indeed, understanding, if fully possessed, establishes a type of dramatic relation between a knower and the world. It places us in the world as agents who are responsive to the range of values and experiences that are the mark of human reality. Recall that the term “drama” itself comes to us from the Greek for “action” or “deed” ( drama ; adj. dramatikos ), and “dramatic” has in its more contemporary usage the sense of doing something with a certain emotional investment or charge (see Shusterman 2001 for a discussion of this). These are, in effect, the markers of the form of understanding I have tried to outline here.

Literature and the Embodiment of Understanding

So what does all of this allow us to say about the thesis of literary cognitivism? How might this offer a foundation for developing our intuition that literary works, while not in the business of stating truths about the world, still have much to show us about it?

I think that the first thing we should want to say is this: what literary representations are able to do especially well is take the concepts we bring to our reading of a work and present them back to us as concrete forms of human engagement. When we read Notes from Underground or Bartleby the Scrivener , we see suffering and alienation presented not as mere “ideas” but as very precisely shaped human situations. And this contextualization of these concepts, this act of presenting them to us in concrete form, is literature's contribution to understanding, the particular light it has to shine on our world. Literary works do not embody conceptual knowledge, if by this we mean that they offer an elaboration of the nature of some aspect of our world, delivered, as it were, in a propositional package. Nor need they, if they are to have a claim to cognitive value. If they embody a form of understanding, it will consist in a more literal act of embodiment, namely, in the capacity of a literary narrative to give shape, form, and structure to the range of values, concerns, and experiences that define human reality.

The vision of life we find in literary narratives shows us human practice and circumstance not from an abstracted, external perspective but from the “inside” of life, in its full dramatic form. And if the argument I gave in the last section is convincing, we can now see how this dramatic presentation of life might be a very important cognitive achievement. This achievement does not consist in the stating of truths or the offering of knowledge of matters of fact. It is rather a matter of literature's ability to open up for us a world of value and significance and of all that this implies about our capacity to understand fully the import of various forms of human activity. Literary works’ mode of engaging with the world is never narrowly or purely cognitive. Literature would not be dramatic if it were. But it is precisely this drama we need if we are to have a textual form that is capable of documenting our particular way in the world. And this is not a minor accomplishment from the cognitive point of view. It shows literature to be among the richest, most potent media we have for the articulation of cultural understanding.

When literary works are successful dramatic achievements, it is always in part because they fashion a sense of what is at stake in the specific regions of human circumstance they represent. In this respect, there is an interesting parallel between literary narratives and moral responses. Just as a moral response does not so much convey knowledge of an event as it gives expression to an agent's awareness of its significance, literary works, rather than stating truths about our world, bring to light the consequence, the import, of those aspects of reality they bring before us. Put differently, literary works represent ways of acknowledging the world rather than knowing it (see Gibson 2003 , 2008; Cavell 1969 ). A literary narrative is in effect a sustained dramatic gesture, a way not only of presenting some content or material but also of responding to it. What we see distilled into the narrative perspective is a vision of how and why this content counts , the precise respects in which it might matter.

These patterns of significance, value, and meaning we find in literary works are patterns to which we tend to have no cognitive access in our in less dramatic, quotidian lives. We simply do not see what Eldridge felicitously calls the “complex texture of our human lives” with such precision of detail and depth of vision in our everyday encounters with the world. We very likely knew what racism is, or that a lynching is among its most brutal manifestations, before reading James Baldwin's short story “Going to Meet the Man.” But unless we have engaged in the very practices Baldwin depicts in his story—and one would hope that few of us have—we have not been granted an understanding of the form they may take as specific types of human activity. Baldwin's manner of representing the desires, repressions, pursuits, and relationships of the characters he imagines for us—indeed, the precise manner in which he develops racism as a theme that structures the story itself—is itself a way of acknowledging what racism is. That is, it constitutes an attempt to render explicit its significance and import in the context of our cultural practices. And in following the story, we too are forced to acknowledge something about the nature of racism, for instance, that it can have its source in something other than just hatred and ignorance, contrary to what we were often told in school. It might reside in something much more primitive and pervasive, something that reaches all the way to the core of our social and sexual natures. For this reason, Baldwin's story forces us to see racism as more complex, and so more terrifying, than we had once thought, or were willing to think.

Literature does not treat the world as an object of knowledge but as a subject of human concern. And this itself is a cognitive accomplishment, a way of bearing witness to the world. Indeed, this gives us reason to speak of literature as engaged in a form of worldly investigation, just of a sort that is markedly different than we find in works of inquiry. It is a dramatic investigation. But human life itself is dramatic in nature, and thus literary works, in their uniquely literary form, are perfectly built for its exploration. Literary works needn't cast aside their literary pursuits and mimic works of philosophy if they are to engage in this form of investigation. They simply need to go about their usual business.

If this is so, then we can respect the textual constraint when defending literary cognitivism, for the form of insight literature trades in is bound up with the internal structure of a literary work—in fact, it is inseparable from it. The insight into life we find in a great novel is the novel itself. It is woven into the fabric of the story, the specific ways in which it configures and gives dramatic expression to its subject matter. Thus, we should not ask whether literary works might be able to do what standard works of inquiry do if we wish to defend literary cognitivism. They do not, nor should we wish them to. We can leave them be as they are, without worrying that we will thereby make them cognitively trivial on account of it.

Instead of asking whether literary works might be able to offer us what other works of inquiry do, a more interesting way of putting the matter is to ask what aspects of our world would be left undocumented, unaccounted for, if we had no literary works. If we think of texts as archives in which we store the various accounts we have to offer of the nature of our world, what would be missing if there were no literary works? The question itself is likely imponderable, for if literary works play an important role in the articulation of cultural understanding, then our sense of our world is itself at least partly literary in origin. At any rate, what we would lack without literary works (and works of art more generally), what would be missing from our archive, is not a body of knowledge but a certain perspective. It would be, of course, the human perspective, that purchase on the world that reveals not what we know about it but how we go about living in it. Without this, we really wouldn't have much to show for ourselves.

Beardsley, M. ( 1981 ). “ Fiction as Representation, ” Synthese , 46, 291–313. 10.1007/BF01130042

Google Scholar

Carroll, N. ( 1998 ). “Art, Narrative, and Moral Understanding.” In   J. Levinson (ed.), Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Preview

Cavell, S. ( 1969 ). “Knowing and Acknowledging.” In Cavell, Must We Mean What We Say? A Book of Essays . New York: Charles Scribner's Sons.

Cohen, T. ( 2004 ). “Metaphor, Feeling, and Narrative.” In   E. John and D. Lopes (eds.), Philosophy of Literature: Contemporary and Classic Readings . Oxford: Blackwell.

Currie, G. ( 1998 ). “Realism of Character and the Value of Fiction.” In   J. Levinson (ed.), Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Davies, S. ( 2000 ). “Fiction.” In   B. Gaut and D. Lopes (eds.), Routledge Companion to Aesthetics . London: Routledge.

Davis, T. ( 1996 ). Humanism . London: Routledge.

Richard Woodfield (ed.), Proceedings: XIth International Congress in Aesthetics. Nottingham: Nnottingham Polytechnic Press.

Doležal, L. ( 1998 ). Heterocosmica. Fiction and Possible Worlds . Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Eldridge, R. ( 2003 ). An Introduction to the Philosophy of Art . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Fish, S. ( 1980 ). Is There a Text in This Class? The Authority of Interpretive Communities . Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Frege, G. ( 1970 ). “On Sense and Reference.” In   P. Geach and M. Black (eds. and trans.), Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege . Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1892).

Gaut, B. ( 2006 ). “Art and Cognition.” In   M. Kieran (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art . Oxford: Blackwell.

Gibson, J. ( 2003 ). “ Between Truth and Triviality. ” British Journal of Aesthetics , 43, 224–37. 10.1093/bjaesthetics/43.3.224

———. ( 2008 ). Fiction and the Weave of Life . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Graham, G. ( 1995 ). “ Learning from Art. ” British Journal of Aesthetics , 35, 26–37. 10.1093/bjaesthetics/35.1.26

Harold, J. ( 2003 ). “ Flexing the Imagination. ” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 61, 247–58. 10.1111/1540-6245.00110

Harrison, B. ( 1991 ). Inconvenient Fictions: Fiction and the Limits of Theory . New Haven: Yale University Press.

John, E. ( 1998 ). “ Readiing Fiction and Conceptual Knowledge: Philosophical Thought in Literary Context. ” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56, 331–48. 10.2307/432124

——— ( 2003 ). “Literary Fiction and the Philosophical Value of Detail.” In   M. Kieran and D. M. Lopes (eds.), Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts . London: Routledge.

Kivy, P. ( 1997 ). Philosophies of Arts: An Essay in Differences . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Lamarque, P. ( 1996 ). Fictional Points of View . Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.

———. ( 2006 .) “Cognitive Values in the Arts: Marking the Boundaries.” In   M. Kieran (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art . Oxford: Blackwell.

Lamarque, P. , and S. H. Olsen . ( 1994 ). Truth, Fiction and Literature . Oxford: Clarendon.

Lewis, D. ( 1978 ). “ Truth in Fiction. ” American Philosophical Quarterly 15, 37–46.

Mulhall, S. ( 1994 ). Stanley Cavell: Philosophy's Recounting of the Ordinary . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

New, C. ( 1999 ). Philosophy of Literature: An Introduction . London: Routledge.

Novitz, D. ( 1987 ). Knowledge, Fiction and Imagination . Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Nussbaum, M. ( 1990 ). Love's Knowledge . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Pavel, T. ( 1986 ). Fictional Worlds . Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Searle, J. ( 1974 –75). “ The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse. ” New Literary History , 6, 319–32. 10.2307/468422

Shusterman, R. ( 2001 ). “ Art as Dramatization ” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 59, 363–72.

Stolnitz, J. ( 1992 ). “ On the Cognitive Triviality of Art. ” British Journal of Aesthetics , 32, 191–200. 10.1093/bjaesthetics/32.3.191

Walton, K. ( 1990 ). Mimesis as Make-Believe . Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

———. ( 1997 ). “Spelunking, Simulation, and Slime: On Being Moved by Fiction.” In   M. Hjort and S. Laver (eds.), Emotion and the Arts . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Weston, M. ( 2001 ). Literature, Philosophy and the Human Good . London: Routledge.

White, H. ( 1978 ). Tropics of Discourse . Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2023 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

  • More from M-W
  • To save this word, you'll need to log in. Log In

Definition of literature

Example sentences.

These examples are programmatically compiled from various online sources to illustrate current usage of the word 'literature.' Any opinions expressed in the examples do not represent those of Merriam-Webster or its editors. Send us feedback about these examples.

Word History

Middle English, from Anglo-French, from Latin litteratura writing, grammar, learning, from litteratus

15th century, in the meaning defined at sense 4

Phrases Containing literature

  • gray literature

Articles Related to literature

woman sitting on floor holding book in front of her face on pink background

Famous Novels, Last Lines

Needless to say, spoiler alert.

alt 5b5f7903e540d

New Adventures in 'Cli-Fi'

Taking the temperature of a literary genre.

alt 5936bc3414c60

Trending: 'Literature' As Bob Dylan...

Trending: 'Literature' As Bob Dylan Sees It

We know how the Nobel Prize committee defines literature, but how does the dictionary?

Dictionary Entries Near literature

literature search

Cite this Entry

“Literature.” Merriam-Webster.com Dictionary , Merriam-Webster, https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/literature. Accessed 12 Sep. 2023.

Kids Definition

Kids definition of literature, more from merriam-webster on literature.

Nglish: Translation of literature for Spanish Speakers

Britannica English: Translation of literature for Arabic Speakers

Britannica.com: Encyclopedia article about literature

Subscribe to America's largest dictionary and get thousands more definitions and advanced search—ad free!

Play Quordle: Guess all four words in a limited number of tries.  Each of your guesses must be a real 5-letter word.

Can you solve 4 words at once?

Word of the day.

See Definitions and Examples »

Get Word of the Day daily email!

a group of lemurs

School of Writing, Literature, and Film

  • Course Descriptions
  • BA in English
  • BA in Creative Writing
  • About Film Studies
  • Film Faculty
  • Minor in Film Studies
  • Film Studies at Work
  • Minor in English
  • Minor in Writing
  • Minor in Applied Journalism
  • Scientific, Technical, and Professional Communication Certificate
  • Academic Advising
  • Student Resources
  • Scholarships
  • MA in English
  • MFA in Creative Writing
  • Master of Arts in Interdisciplinary Studies (MAIS)
  • Low Residency MFA in Creative Writing
  • Fall 2023 Undergraduate Course Descriptions
  • Fall 2023 Graduate Course Descriptions
  • Faculty & Staff Directory
  • Faculty by Fields of Focus
  • Faculty Notes Submission Form
  • Promoting Your Research
  • 2023 Spring Newsletter
  • Commitment to DEI
  • Twitter News Feed
  • SWLF Media Channel
  • Student Work
  • View All Events
  • The Stone Award
  • Conference for Antiracist Teaching, Language and Assessment
  • Continuing Education
  • Alumni Notes
  • Featured Alumni
  • Donor Information
  • Support SWLF
  • Make a Gift

What is Literature? || Definition & Examples

"what is literature": a literary guide for english students and teachers.

View the full series: The Oregon State Guide to English Literary Terms

  • Guide to Literary Terms
  • BA in English Degree
  • BA in Creative Writing Degree
  • Oregon State Admissions Info

What is Literature? Transcript (English and Spanish Subtitles Available in Video; Click HERE for Spanish Transcript)

By Evan Gottlieb & Paige Thomas

The question of what makes something literary is an enduring one, and I don’t expect that we’ll answer it fully in this short video. Instead, I want to show you a few different ways that literary critics approach this question and then offer a short summary of the 3 big factors that we must consider when we ask the question ourselves.

Let’s begin by making a distinction between “Literature with a capital L” and “literature with a small l.”

“Literature with a small l” designates any written text: we can talk about “the literature” on any given subject without much difficulty.

“Literature with a capital L”, by contrast, designates a much smaller set of texts – a subset of all the texts that have been written.

what_is_literature_little_l.png

speaker gesturing to literature with a small "l" rather than with a big "L"

So what makes a text literary or what makes a text “Literature with a capital L”?

Let’s start with the word itself.  “Literature” comes from Latin, and it originally meant “the use of letters” or “writing.” But when the word entered the Romance languages that derived from Latin, it took on the additional meaning of “knowledge acquired from reading or studying books.” So we might use this definition to understand “Literature with a Capital L” as writing that gives us knowledge--writing that should be studied.

But this begs the further question: what books or texts are worth studying or close reading ?

For some critics, answering this question is a matter of establishing canonicity.  A work of literature becomes “canonical” when cultural institutions like schools or universities or prize committees classify it as a work of lasting artistic or cultural merit.

The canon, however, has proved problematic as a measure of what “Literature with a capital L” is because the gatekeepers of the Western canon have traditionally been White and male. It was only in the closing decades of the twentieth century that the canon of Literature was opened to a greater inclusion of diverse authors.

And here’s another problem with that definition: if inclusion in the canon were our only definition of Literature, then there could be no such thing as contemporary Literature, which, of course, has not yet stood the test of time.

And here’s an even bigger problem: not every book that receives good reviews or a wins a prize turns out to be of lasting value in the eyes of later readers.

On the other hand, a novel like Herman Melville’s Moby-Di ck, which was NOT received well by critics or readers when it was first published in 1851, has since gone on to become a mainstay of the American literary canon.

moby_dick_with_quote.png

graphic with cover of Melville's "Moby Dick" and quote

As you can see, canonicity is obviously a problematic index of literariness.

So… what’s the alternative?  Well, we could just go with a descriptive definition: “if you love it, then it’s Literature!”

But that’s a little too subjective.  For example, no matter how much you may love a certain book from your childhood (I love The Very Hungry Caterpillar ) that doesn’t automatically make it literary, no matter how many times you’ve re-read it.

Furthermore, the very idea that we should have an emotional attachment to the books we read has its own history that cannot be detached from the rise of the middle class and its politics of telling people how to behave.

Ok, so “literature with a capital L” cannot always by defined by its inclusion in the canon or the fact that it has been well-received so…what is it then? Well, for other critics, what makes something Literature would seem to be qualities within the text itself.

According to the critic Derek Attridge, there are three qualities that define modern Western Literature:

1. a quality of invention or inventiveness in the text itself;

2.  the reader’s sense that what they are reading is singular. In other words, the unique vision of the writer herself.

3. a sense of ‘otherness’ that pushes the reader to see the world around them in a new way

Notice that nowhere in this three-part definition is there any limitation on the content of Literature. Instead, we call something Literature when it affects the reader at the level of style and construction rather than substance.

In other words, Literature can be about anything!

what_is_literature_caterpillar.png

speaker telling a secret with photo of Carle's "The Very Hungry Caterpillar" in the background

The idea that a truly literary text can change a reader is of course older than this modern definition. In the English tradition, poetry was preferred over novels because it was thought to create mature and sympathetic reader-citizens.

Likewise, in the Victorian era, it was argued that reading so-called “great” works of literature was the best way for readers to realize their full spiritual potentials in an increasingly secular world.

But these never tell us precisely what “the best” is.  To make matters worse, as I mentioned already, “the best” in these older definitions was often determined by White men in positions of cultural and economic power.

So we are still faced with the question of whether there is something inherent in a text that makes it literary.

Some critics have suggested that a sense of irony – or, more broadly, a sense that there is more than one meaning to a given set of words – is essential to “Literature with a capital L.”

Reading for irony means reading slowly or at least attentively.  It demands a certain attention to the complexity of the language on the page, whether that language is objectively difficult or not.

In a similar vein, other critics have claimed that the overall effect of a literary text should be one of “defamiliarization,” meaning that the text asks or even forces readers to see the world differently than they did before reading it.

Along these lines, literary theorist Roland Barthes maintained that there were two kinds of texts: the text of pleasure, which we can align with everyday Literature with a small l” and the text of jouissance , (yes, I said jouissance) which we can align with Literature. Jouissance makes more demands on the reader and raises feelings of strangeness and wonder that surpass the everyday and even border on the painful or disorienting.

Barthes’ definition straddles the line between objectivity and subjectivity. Literature differs from the mass of writing by offering more and different kinds of experiences than the ordinary, non-literary text.

Literature for Barthes is thus neither entirely in the eye of the beholder, nor something that can be reduced to set of repeatable, purely intrinsic characteristics.

This negative definition has its own problems, though. If the literary text is always supposed to be innovative and unconventional, then genre fiction, which IS conventional, can never be literary.

So it seems that whatever hard and fast definition we attempt to apply to Literature, we find that we run up against inevitable exceptions to the rules.

As we examine the many problematic ways that people have defined literature, one thing does become clear. In each of the above examples, what counts as Literature depends upon three interrelated factors: the world, the text, and the critic or reader.

You see, when we encounter a literary text, we usually do so through a field of expectations that includes what we’ve heard about the text or author in question [the world], the way the text is presented to us [the text], and how receptive we as readers are to the text’s demands [the reader].

With this in mind, let’s return to where we started. There is probably still something to be said in favor of the “test of time” theory of Literature.

After all, only a small percentage of what is published today will continue to be read 10, 20, or even 100 years from now; and while the mechanisms that determine the longevity of a text are hardly neutral, one can still hope that individual readers have at least some power to decide what will stay in print and develop broader cultural relevance.

The only way to experience what Literature is, then, is to keep reading: as long as there are avid readers, there will be literary texts – past, present, and future – that challenge, excite, and inspire us.

Interested in more video lessons? View the full series:

The oregon state guide to english literary terms, contact info.

Email: [email protected]

College of Liberal Arts Student Services 214 Bexell Hall 541-737-0561

Deans Office 200 Bexell Hall 541-737-4582

Corvallis, OR 97331-8600

liberalartsosu liberalartsosu liberalartsosu liberalartsosu CLA LinkedIn

  • Dean's Office
  • Faculty & Staff Resources
  • Featured Stories
  • Undergraduate Students
  • Transfer Students
  • Graduate Students
  • Career Services
  • Internships
  • Financial Aid
  • Degrees and Programs
  • Centers and Initiatives
  • School of Communication
  • School of History, Philosophy and Religion
  • School of Language, Culture and Society
  • School of Psychological Science
  • School of Public Policy
  • School of Visual, Performing and Design Arts
  • School of Writing, Literature and Film
  • Give to CLA

IMAGES

  1. What is literature

    literature understanding definition

  2. What is Literature?

    literature understanding definition

  3. Definition of Literature for Fundamentals of Literature

    literature understanding definition

  4. PPT

    literature understanding definition

  5. English literature

    literature understanding definition

  6. Literature

    literature understanding definition

VIDEO

  1. The importance of literature

  2. literary terms

  3. LITERATURE Form Three

  4. Sound Devices in Literature: Understanding Epiphora

  5. Ultimate literature ll Most beneficial literary work for you

  6. "Mastering Literary Criticism and Analysis: Your Gateway to Literature!"

COMMENTS

  1. Literature | Definition, Characteristics, Genres, Types, & Facts

    literature, a body of written works. The name has traditionally been applied to those imaginative works of poetry and prose distinguished by the intentions of their authors and the perceived aesthetic excellence of their execution.

  2. What Literature Can Teach Us - ThoughtCo

    Literature is a term used to describe written and sometimes spoken material. Derived from the Latin word literature meaning "writing formed with letters," literature most commonly refers to works of the creative imagination, including poetry, drama, fiction, nonfiction, and in some instances, journalism, and song. What Is Literature?

  3. 1.1: What is Literature? - Humanities LibreTexts

    1: Introduction 1.2: Why Read and Write About Literature? Heather Ringo & Athena Kashyap City College of San Francisco via ASCCC Open Educational Resources Initiative Table of contents Defining Literature In order for us to study literature with any kind of depth, first we must decide what constitutes literature.

  4. Literature and Knowledge | The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy ...

    Abstract. This article presents thoughts about the role of literature as a source of knowledge. It is common to claim that in works of literature we find some of the most powerful representations of reality our culture has to offer. According to this view, the literary perspective is the definitive human perspective and works of literature ...

  5. Literature - Simple English Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

    Literature is a group of works of art that are made of words. Most are written, but some are shared by word of mouth. Literature usually means a work of poetry, theatre or narrative. [1] There are many different kinds of literature, such as poetry, plays, or novels.

  6. Literary Theory | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

    Literary Theory. “Literary theory” is the body of ideas and methods we use in the practical reading of literature. By literary theory we refer not to the meaning of a work of literature but to the theories that reveal what literature can mean. Literary theory is a description of the underlying principles, one might say the tools, by which ...

  7. Literature Definition & Meaning - Merriam-Webster

    -ˌtu̇r 1 a (1) : writings in prose or verse especially : writings having excellence of form or expression and expressing ideas of permanent or universal interest literature stands related to man as science stands to nature J. H. Newman (2) : an example of such writings what came out, though rarely literature, was always a roaring good story People

  8. What is Literature? || Definition & Examples | | College of ...

    1. a quality of invention or inventiveness in the text itself; 2. the reader’s sense that what they are reading is singular. In other words, the unique vision of the writer herself. 3. a sense of ‘otherness’ that pushes the reader to see the world around them in a new way. Notice that nowhere in this three-part definition is there any ...